Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Newton’s Divine Sensorium

When Kant read Newton (and Clarke) the following conceptual space could have been opened up for him: space is neither a substance nor an accident, but is the way in which objects are present to the (divine) mind. Space is the divine sensorium, the means by which God is present to the creation. That...

Full description

Saved in:  
Bibliographic Details
Main Author: Insole, Christopher (Author)
Format: Electronic Article
Language:English
Check availability: HBZ Gateway
Journals Online & Print:
Drawer...
Fernleihe:Fernleihe für die Fachinformationsdienste
Published: University of Pennsylvania Press 2011
In: Journal of the history of ideas
Year: 2011, Volume: 72, Issue: 3, Pages: 413-436
Online Access: Volltext (JSTOR)
Volltext (lizenzpflichtig)
Volltext (lizenzpflichtig)

MARC

LEADER 00000caa a22000002 4500
001 1826564659
003 DE-627
005 20231013160917.0
007 cr uuu---uuuuu
008 221208s2011 xx |||||o 00| ||eng c
024 7 |a 10.1353/jhi.2011.0025  |2 doi 
035 |a (DE-627)1826564659 
035 |a (DE-599)KXP1826564659 
040 |a DE-627  |b ger  |c DE-627  |e rda 
041 |a eng 
084 |a 0  |2 ssgn 
100 1 |a Insole, Christopher  |e VerfasserIn  |4 aut 
245 1 0 |a Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Newton’s Divine Sensorium 
264 1 |c 2011 
336 |a Text  |b txt  |2 rdacontent 
337 |a Computermedien  |b c  |2 rdamedia 
338 |a Online-Ressource  |b cr  |2 rdacarrier 
520 |a When Kant read Newton (and Clarke) the following conceptual space could have been opened up for him: space is neither a substance nor an accident, but is the way in which objects are present to the (divine) mind. Space is the divine sensorium, the means by which God is present to the creation. That objects have a spatial form occurs insofar as objects are dependent upon and known by (divine) mind. Such a conceptual space, transposed (with some modifications) to the human cognitive mind, might plausibly—both philosophically and historically speaking—have helped Kant along the road to transcendental idealism. 
773 0 8 |i Enthalten in  |t Journal of the history of ideas  |d Philadelphia, Pa. : University of Pennsylvania Press, 1940  |g 72(2011), 3, Seite 413-436  |h Online-Ressource  |w (DE-627)300186193  |w (DE-600)1481685-4  |w (DE-576)09444921X  |x 1086-3222  |7 nnns 
773 1 8 |g volume:72  |g year:2011  |g number:3  |g pages:413-436 
856 |3 Volltext  |u http://www.jstor.org/stable/23011290  |x JSTOR 
856 4 0 |u https://doi.org/10.1353/jhi.2011.0025  |x Resolving-System  |z lizenzpflichtig  |3 Volltext 
856 4 0 |u https://muse.jhu.edu/pub/56/article/445504  |x Verlag  |z lizenzpflichtig  |3 Volltext 
951 |a AR 
ELC |a 1 
ITA |a 1  |t 1 
LOK |0 000 xxxxxcx a22 zn 4500 
LOK |0 001 4228385559 
LOK |0 003 DE-627 
LOK |0 004 1826564659 
LOK |0 005 20231013160917 
LOK |0 008 221208||||||||||||||||ger||||||| 
LOK |0 035   |a (DE-Tue135)IxTheo#2022-12-01#4F5657D7E1668D2136EAC7CF2844D6E21FE0BC3E 
LOK |0 040   |a DE-Tue135  |c DE-627  |d DE-Tue135 
LOK |0 092   |o n 
LOK |0 852   |a DE-Tue135 
LOK |0 852 1  |9 00 
LOK |0 866   |x JSTOR#http://www.jstor.org/stable/23011290 
LOK |0 935   |a ixzs  |a ixrk  |a zota 
ORI |a SA-MARC-ixtheoa001.raw 
REL |a 1 
SUB |a REL